Jump to content

Felicific calculus: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Tags: Mobile edit Mobile app edit Android app edit
Tags: Mobile edit Mobile app edit Android app edit
Line 34: Line 34:
Based on the first volume of his complete works there is four deriving classification or distinct object of civil law <ref>Principles of The Civil Code (Part one, Ch. II)</ref> that is known as known in his penal laws: of [[Security]], [[Subsistence]], [[Abundance]], [[Equality]].
Based on the first volume of his complete works there is four deriving classification or distinct object of civil law <ref>Principles of The Civil Code (Part one, Ch. II)</ref> that is known as known in his penal laws: of [[Security]], [[Subsistence]], [[Abundance]], [[Equality]].
There is also four sanctions that he defined, they are: [[Physical]], [[Political]], [[Moral]] (this is as a result social or legal and can lead to [[popular]] sanction), and [[Religious]].
There is also four sanctions that he defined, they are: [[Physical]], [[Political]], [[Moral]] (this is as a result social or legal and can lead to [[popular]] sanction), and [[Religious]].
<blockquote>
<blockquote> Sanctions. Since the Traites, others have been discovered. There are now, I. Human: six, viz. 1. Physical; 2. Retributive; 3. Sympathetic; 4. Antipathetic; 5. Popular, or Moral; 6. Political, including Legal and Administrative.<ref>from an extract from a letter of Bentham’s to Dumont, dated Oct. 28, 1821 </ref> </blockquote>
“Sanctions. Since the Traites, others have been discovered. There are now, I. Human: six, viz. 1. Physical; 2. Retributive; 3. Sympathetic; 4. Antipathetic; 5. Popular, or Moral; 6. Political, including Legal and Administrative.

“II. Superhuman vice Religious: all exemplifiable in the case of drunkenness; viz. the punitory class.

“Note—Sanctions in genere duæ, punitoriæ et remuneratoriæ; in serie, septem ut super; seven multiplied by two, equal fourteen.

“The Judicatory of the popular or moral sanction has two Sections: that of the few, and that of the many: Aristocratical and Democratical: their laws, their decisions, are to a vast extent opposite.”<ref>from an extract from a letter of Bentham’s to Dumont, dated Oct. 28, 1821 </ref>
</blockquote>
Further he base <big>a pleasure</big> or <big>a pain</big>, or of benefit and mischief, that is in method applied by knowing more of it from those seven above mentioned references that are after to apply it to a respective purpose, else it is blindfolded. <ref>Complete works of Jeremy Bentham, Westminster version (Vol. 1 of 11)</ref>
Further he base <big>a pleasure</big> or <big>a pain</big>, or of benefit and mischief, that is in method applied by knowing more of it from those seven above mentioned references that are after to apply it to a respective purpose, else it is blindfolded. <ref>Complete works of Jeremy Bentham, Westminster version (Vol. 1 of 11)</ref>
<blockquote> Property and law are born and must die together. Before the laws, there was no property: take away the laws, all property ceases. <ref>Principles of The Civil Code</ref></blockquote>
<blockquote> Property and law are born and must die together. Before the laws, there was no property: take away the laws, all property ceases. <ref>Principles of The Civil Code</ref></blockquote>

Revision as of 07:58, 29 December 2022

The felicific calculus is an algorithm formulated by utilitarian philosopher Jeremy Bentham (1747–1832) for calculating the degree or amount of pleasure that a specific action is likely to induce. Bentham, an ethical hedonist, believed the moral rightness or wrongness of an action to be a function of the amount of pleasure or pain that it produced. The felicific calculus could, in principle at least, determine the moral status of any considered act. The algorithm is also known as the utility calculus, the hedonistic calculus and the hedonic calculus.

To be included in this calculation are several variables (or vectors), which Bentham called "circumstances". These are:

  1. Intensity: How strong is the pleasure?
  2. Duration: How long will the pleasure last (its magnitude is composed)?
  3. Certainty or uncertainty: How likely or unlikely is it that the pleasure will occur (its probability)?
  4. Propinquity or remoteness: How soon will the pleasure occur (measured by its opposite)?
  5. Fecundity: The probability that the action will be followed by sensations of the same kind (is measured from a pain).
  6. Purity: The probability that it will not be followed by sensations of the opposite kind (from a pleasure).
  7. Extent: How many people will be affected (for example the number of people)?

Bentham's instructions

To take an exact account of the general tendency of any act, by which the interests of a community are affected, proceed as follows. Begin with any one person of those whose interests seem most immediately to be affected by it: and take an account,

  • Of the value of each distinguishable pleasure which appears to be produced by it in the first instance.
  • Of the value of each pain which appears to be produced by it in the first instance.
  • Of the value of each pleasure which appears to be produced by it after the first. This constitutes the fecundity of the first pleasure and the impurity of the first pain.
  • Of the value of each pain which appears to be produced by it after the first. This constitutes the fecundity of the first pain, and the impurity of the first pleasure.
  • Sum up all the values of all the pleasures on the one side, and those of all the pains on the other. The balance, if it be on the side of pleasure, will give the good tendency of the act upon the whole, with respect to the interests of that individual person; if on the side of pain, the bad tendency of it upon the whole.
  • Take an account of the number of persons whose interests appear to be concerned; and repeat the above process with respect to each. Sum up the numbers expressive of the degrees of good tendency, which the act has, with respect to each individual, in regard to whom the tendency of it is good upon the whole. Do this again with respect to each individual, in regard to whom the tendency of it is bad upon the whole. Take the balance which if on the side of pleasure, will give the general good tendency of the act, with respect to the total number or community of individuals concerned; if on the side of pain, the general evil tendency, with respect to the same community.[1]

To make his proposal easier to remember, Bentham devised what he called a "mnemonic doggerel" (also referred to as "memoriter verses"), which synthesized "the whole fabric of morals and legislation":

Intense, long, certain, speedy, fruitful, pure—

Such marks in pleasures and in pains endure.
Such pleasures seek if private be thy end:
If it be public, wide let them extend
Such pains avoid, whichever be thy view:

If pains must come, let them extend to few.

Note

Based on the first volume of his complete works there is four deriving classification or distinct object of civil law [2] that is known as known in his penal laws: of Security, Subsistence, Abundance, Equality. There is also four sanctions that he defined, they are: Physical, Political, Moral (this is as a result social or legal and can lead to popular sanction), and Religious.

“Sanctions. Since the Traites, others have been discovered. There are now, I. Human: six, viz. 1. Physical; 2. Retributive; 3. Sympathetic; 4. Antipathetic; 5. Popular, or Moral; 6. Political, including Legal and Administrative.

“II. Superhuman vice Religious: all exemplifiable in the case of drunkenness; viz. the punitory class.

“Note—Sanctions in genere duæ, punitoriæ et remuneratoriæ; in serie, septem ut super; seven multiplied by two, equal fourteen.

“The Judicatory of the popular or moral sanction has two Sections: that of the few, and that of the many: Aristocratical and Democratical: their laws, their decisions, are to a vast extent opposite.”[3]

Further he base a pleasure or a pain, or of benefit and mischief, that is in method applied by knowing more of it from those seven above mentioned references that are after to apply it to a respective purpose, else it is blindfolded. [4]

Property and law are born and must die together. Before the laws, there was no property: take away the laws, all property ceases. [5]

Hedons and dolors

The units of measurements used in the felicific calculus may be termed hedons and dolors.[6]

See also

References

  1. ^ * Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, London, 1789
  2. ^ Principles of The Civil Code (Part one, Ch. II)
  3. ^ from an extract from a letter of Bentham’s to Dumont, dated Oct. 28, 1821
  4. ^ Complete works of Jeremy Bentham, Westminster version (Vol. 1 of 11)
  5. ^ Principles of The Civil Code
  6. ^ San Diego University – Glossary Archived May 9, 2008, at the Wayback Machine by Lawrence M. Hinman